Professor Philip Goff has published an exploratory piece for general readers about the so-called hard problem of consciousness. For mainstream philosophy, psychology and science, consciousness is a problem as it is difficult to fit it into a materialist worldview, one where everything is ultimately reducible to physics, via biology. Thus, as he says, science does not have an explanation of how the brain produces the inner world of sensations. The physiological processes could have occurred without conscious experience existing at all, as Goff explains below. His own explanation is that of panpsychism, that matter has a mental aspect to it: https://www.amazon.com/Consciousness-Everywhere-Panpsychism-Journal-Studies/dp/1788360877. But it does not seem to solve the problem of human consciousness, if say electrons have a proto-consciousness. How does human consciousness arise from this? The problem is just multiplied.
This debate that has gone on for centuries is conducted within the framework of scientific materialism. It is hard to find a scientist rejecting this framework, as that is their day job bread and butter. But, for the free thinker, that conclusion seems clear; the problem is not consciousness, but scientific materialism.
How does consciousness and freewill arise in a material universe? It does not, as the universe is not a closed material system, that is the logical conclusion of that problem. As I see it, both consciousness and freewill are creations of God, and exist by His being. It is as simple as that; problem solved. Indeed, the existence of consciousness is one of the best arguments for the existence of God, as the materialists admit that they have no answers themselves. Goff mentions this point but brushes over it. It is just politically incorrect now to appeal to God.
https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/the-mystery-of-consciousness-is-deeper-than-we-thought/
"Despite great progress, we lack even the beginning of an explanation of how the brain produces our inner world of colors, sounds, smells and tastes. A thought experiment with "pain-pleasure" zombies illustrates that the mystery is deeper than we thought.
In the 1990s the Australian philosopher David Chalmers famously framed the challenge of distinguishing between the "easy" problems and the "hard" problem of consciousness. Easy problems focus on explaining behavior, such as the ability to discriminate, categorize and react to surprises. Still incredibly challenging, they're "easy" in the sense that they fit into standard scientific explanation: we postulate a mechanism to explain how the system—the brain—does what it does.
The hard problem comes after we've explained all of these functions of the brain, where we are still left with a puzzle: Why is the carrying out of these functions accompanied by experience? Why doesn't all this mechanistic functioning go on "in the dark"? In my own work, I have argued that the hard problem is rooted in the way that the "father of modern science," Galileo, designed physical science to exclude consciousness.
Chalmers made the quandary vivid by promoting the idea of a "philosophical zombie," a complicated mechanism set up to behave exactly like a human being and with the same information processing in its brain, but with no consciousness. You stick a knife in such a zombie, and it screams and runs away. But it doesn't actually feel pain. When a philosophical zombie crosses the street, it carefully checks that there is no traffic, but it doesn't actually have any visual or auditory experience of the street.
Nobody thinks zombies are real, but they offer a vivid way of working out where you stand on the hard problem. Those on Team Chalmers believe that if all there was to a human being were the mechanistic processes of physical science, we'd all be zombies. Given that we're not zombies, there must be something more going on in us to explain our consciousness. Solving the hard problem is then a matter of working out the extra ingredient, with one increasingly popular option being to posit very rudimentary forms of consciousness at the level of fundamental particles or fields.
For the opposing team, such as the late, great philosopher Daniel Dennett, this division between feeling and behavior makes no sense. The only task for a science of consciousness is explaining behavior, not just the external behavior of the organism but also that of its inner parts. This debate has rattled on for decades.
However, there has more recently been a new and interesting development in these philosophical debates. Growing numbers of philosophers suspect that the division between "feelings" and "behavior," inspired by zombies and by the distinction between "hard" and "easy" problems, poses an even deeper challenge than Chalmers foresaw. This may tempt us to think Dennett was right after all, and the whole "hard problem" setup is a chimera.
Or it may lead us to think that the mind is more mysterious than has thus far been appreciated.
The problem is that once we commit to the possibility of zombies, we can't just stop at vanilla ones. If it makes sense to separate out consciousness and behavioral functioning, then it also makes sense to "mix and match" them in weird ways. We could imagine, for example, color inverts, who are physically just like us, but when they look at bananas, they have the same experience of color that we have when we look at tomatoes, and vice versa. Many teenagers first get into thinking about philosophy through musing on such possibilities (too often, admittedly, in dorm rooms).
Here's a stranger kind of mix-and-match zombie: pain-pleasure inverts. Pain-pleasure inverts behave just like us but feel pleasure when we feel pain and vice versa. So when you stick a knife in a pain-pleasure invert, they feel great pleasure, but this pleasure causes them to scream and run away. When a pain-pleasure invert eats and drinks, they feel terrible pain, but this pain causes them to keep eating and drinking.
Something seems wrong here: pain-pleasure inverts seem nonsensical. But if we accept Chalmers' conceptual distinction between behavioral functioning and subjective experience, then pain-pleasure inverts ought to be just as conceivable as regular zombies. The only way to reject the coherence of pain-pleasure inverts is to reject the initial division between the "easy" problems of behavior and the "hard" problems of conscious experience.
I argue a lot about philosophy on social media, and I've found many people thinking evolution would explain why we're not pain-pleasure inverts. But if you think about it carefully, that doesn't make sense. Natural selection is only going to be motivated to make me feel pain when my body is damaged if that feeling is going to lead me to avoid getting my body damaged. If we lived in the bizarre universe of pain-pleasure inverts, where pleasure generally leads to avoidance behavior and pain to attraction behavior, then we would have evolved to feel pleasure when our body is damaged and pain when we eat and drink. Pain-pleasure inverts that eat and reproduce would pass on their genes just as well as us. In other words, evolutionary explanations of our consciousness presuppose that we're not pain-pleasure inverts, just as they presuppose the existence of self-replicating life. In either case, evolution cannot explain what it already assumes.
Why does this matter? If consciousness and behavior could come apart in other possible universes, then we need to explain not only why they come together in the human brain but also why they come together in a rational and coherent way. This has become known as the mystery of psychophysical harmony. The pain-pleasure examples are just the most vivid case. More generally any historical or sociological explanation (for example, of why people voted a certain way in an election) assumes that human beings respond in a more or less rational way to their conscious beliefs and desires. But if we are physical objects in a meaningless, purposeless universe, why should our behavior and our consciousness match together in a coherent and rational way? Why aren't we some kind of weird mix-and-match zombies?
Some philosophers have argued that psychophysical harmony points to God. I think that's a bit of an overreaction, but I have argued that dealing with psychophysical harmony takes us in radical directions, uprooting our most fundamental assumptions about reality. Since the scientific revolution, we have conceived of laws of nature as working from past to present, ensuring that what happens in the present is dependent on what happened a moment earlier. I believe we can make rigorous scientific sense of teleological laws that work from future to present, ensuring that what happens in the present is dependent on the need to get closer to some future goal, such as the goal of harmonious alignment of consciousness and behavior."